Monday 4 March 2013

Why a God-man?: A Reading of Anselm's 'Cur Deus Homo'



               In his well-known article "Anselm on the Cost of Salvation,"[1] Brian Leftow represents an argument that Anselm's student Boso presents on behalf of certain "unbelievers" who reject the Incarnation on the grounds of its unfittingness. That representation may be illustrated as follows: first, let P stand for "God saves humanity without becoming incarnate and dying for our sins, and his saving us in this way does not result in an unacceptable balance of good and evil in the world." Now:
(1) God is perfectly wise. (premise)
(2) If God is perfectly wise, he pays no unjustified, avoidable costs to save humanity. (premise)
(3) Therefore, God pays no unjustified, avoidable costs to save humanity. (1, 2, MP)
(4) God is omnipotent. (premise)
(5) If God is omnipotent, then (if P is possible, God can bring it about that P). (premise)
(6) Therefore, if P is possible, God can bring it about that P.  (4, 5, MP)
(7) P is possible. (premise)
(8) Therefore, God can bring it about that P.
(9) If God can bring it about that P, then (if God becomes incarnate or atones, he pays an unjustified, avoidable cost to save humanity). (premise)
(10) Therefore, if God becomes incarnate or atones, he pays an unjustified, avoidable cost to save humanity. (8, 9, MP)
(11) Therefore, God does not become incarnate or atone. (3, 10, MT) 
Now, according to Leftow, the most promising approach for Anselm or anyone sympathetic to his concerns with respect to CDH is to argue against either premise (7) or premise (9).
            Leftow believes, moreover, that Anselm finally settles for arguing against (9) rather than (7). His reason for this is that in order to show that (7) is false, Anselm would have to argue that the following two claims are necessarily false.
(LC): If God offers humanity salvation, he does so via some lesser compensation for sin.
(NC): If God offers humanity salvation, he does so without any compensation for sin.
Anselm's reply to the first possibility, according to Leftow, is to argue that God cannot allow humans some lesser form of compensation because this would spoil God's plan for humanity, in which God had originally planned to make humans the equal of angels in being subject only to himself.[2] However, Leftow notes, on this account it is merely contingent that God does not offer humanity a lesser form of compensation for sin. Hence, on this account, it is still possible that (7) obtains. Leftow also seems to take the line of reasoning Anselm offers against LC as his reasoning against NC, which, if God cannot allow humans lesser compensation because they need to have a certain character to be the equal of the angels, it also makes sense that he would take this as a case against NC. So, Leftow concludes, Anselm must argue against (9). Leftow then proceeds to give two reasons for doubting (9), one of which he claims is Anselm's.
            The reason Leftow ascribes to Anselm is that although God could have saved humanity in some other way (in terms of absolute possibility), the way in which God chose was not unjustified, and this was because the Incarnation was satisfactory in terms of its poetic beauty or fittingness. Here, Leftow invokes CDH 2.11 in which Anselm appeals to such criteria for showing that God's decision to become incarnate was neither unjustified nor foolish:[3]
If a man sinned through pleasure, is it not fitting that he should give recompense through pain? And if it was in the easiest possible way that man was defeated by the devil, so as to dishonour God by his sinning, is it not justice that man, in giving recompense for sin, should, for the honour of God, defeat the devil with the greatest possible difficulty? Is it not fitting that man, who, by sinning, removed himself as far as he possibly could away from God, should, as recompense to God, make a gift of himself in an act of the greatest possible self-giving?[4]
By appealing to the criteria of fittingness or beauty, therefore, Leftow thinks Anselm can block (9), and thereby defeat the argument Boso presents. For, even if some other means are available by which God can offer man salvation, God does not pay an unjustified cost in becoming incarnate and dying upon a cross for the sake of mortal man.
            But as Visser and Williams have argued, Leftow's claim that Anselm relies on beauty or fittingness as a means of blocking the argument against the Incarnation might be less direct. According to Visser and Williams, Anselm does not rely on fittingness or beauty as rational support for the Incarnation until after he has given an argument for its truth.[5] And, here, the point of bringing such criteria to the table, they claim, is not to give philosophical support for the Incarnation, but to show its attractiveness once the case for its being true has been made.[6]  In support for this last claim, they cite a long passage in which Boso insists that Anselm should not rely on fittingness or other aesthetics concerns for justifying the Incarnation until after he has made his case by argument alone.
All these are beautiful notions, and are to be viewed like pictures. But if there is nothing solid underlying them, they do not seem to unbelievers to provide sufficient grounds why we should believe that God wished to suffer the things of which we are speaking ... What has to be demonstrated, therefore, is the logical soundness of the truth, that is: cogent reason which proves that God ought to have, or could have, humbled himself for the purposes which we proclaim. Then, in order that the physical reality of the truth, so to speak, may shine forth all the more, these appropriatenesses may be set out as pictorial representations of this physical reality.[7]
As Visser and Williams note, Anselm does not quibble with Boso's insistence but seems to concede to it.
            Moreover, there is some reason to think that Anselm has an alternative response against LC and NC than the one Leftow has argued that Anselm actually provides. Leftow objects, one should recall, to the claim that Anselm argues that it is necessary that, by his goodness,[8] "God complete whatever he has begun in human beings" (CDH, 2.4). Here, Leftow's claim is based on the idea that to affirm that God's goodness made it necessary that God completes whatever God begins in humanity, Anselm would have to rule out the possibility that either (LC) if God offers humanity salvation, he does so via some lesser compensation for sin or (NC) if God offers humanity salvation, he does so without any compensation for sin. And Leftow argues that Anselm thinks LC is possibly true (and thus only possibly false), so he acknowledges that God can possibly bring it about that humanity is offered salvation without God's becoming incarnate.
            Indeed, Anselm does seem to argue against LC in a manner which implies that LC is only contingently false, by contending that humans are necessary to populate the heavens, following the fall of the bad angels, and that these humans must necessarily possess the same character as the good angels. But he also gives another argument that, if true, implies that LC is necessarily false. His argument that I have in mind is this: Anselm claims that if humans sin against God, humans cannot in their sinful state, make good on the reparation they owe God.[9] The reason for their inability, he claims, is due to the fact that everything they could possibly give to God as payment of their debt are things that they already owe him. Thus, if there is no means by which man can pay off his debt, there is no lesser, i.e., moderate, option by which God could offer atonement. But this does not yet, of course, address the question why God cannot simply remit the debt that man owes him.
Atonement without Satisfaction?
            To the suggestion that God simply pardons the sin without reparation, Anselm offers the following line of reasoning. One might call the argument he gives the universal order argument. The major premise of Anselm's syllogism is that "there is nothing more intolerable in the whole universal creation that a creature should take away honor from the Creator and fail to repay what he takes away."[10] The minor premise is that "therefore, nothing is more unjust than that a creature should take away honor from the Creator without giving it back."[11] Assuming the syllogism is valid, then, the conclusion, of course, is that "therefore, nothing is more unjust than that a creature should take away honor from the Creator without giving it back."[12] One minor difficulty for assessing the validity of Anselm's syllogism is that it is not immediately clear from the context what he means by "intolerable." He cannot mean "intolerable" in the sense of fittingness or a certain poetic beauty, since he has already agreed not to appeal to such things in arguing against "unbelievers." The other serious alternative for "intolerable" is "injustice," and this seems not only a sensible suggestion, but necessary if one is to connect the major premise and minor premise. For, if God is a being of unequaled dignity, an offense against God will count, a fortiori, as an equaled offense or insult and thereby an unequaled injustice.
            However, this argument, although it seems convincing, completely fails to address the question why God would require recompense at all. For why couldn't God, being a being of unequaled mercy as well as justice, simply forgo the requirement for satisfaction for humanity's sin? In this regard, Anselm offers several other attempts to address the question, but most of them do not seem successful. One reply that has already received some attention is that in which Anselm argues that God intended to use Adam's race replace the angels who fell from the heavens from their disobedience. In this case, these humans would need to be virtuous in character -- the equal of the good angels who maintained obedience to God. But this argument, as Leftow has already noted, will imply that (LC) is only contingently false, and thus it cannot feature in any attempt to argue that LC is necessarily false.
            Another reply that Anselm gives is that God cannot simply forgive sins because he must punish them.  
To forgive a sin in this way is nothing other than to refrain from inflicting punishment. And if no satisfaction is given, the way to regulate sin correctly is none other than to punish it. If, therefore, it is not punished, it is forgiven without its having been regulated.[13]
Anselm does not immediately provide an argument for his claim that if no satisfaction is given, the proper way to regulate a sin is to punish it. However, he does provide a second argument that can be seen as support for this claim. His second argument is that if God does not punish a sinner, the sinner's position will be similar to the non-sinner's before God.[14] But, arguably, this is a non-sequitur. For, rather than punishing the sinner, God could simply reward the non-sinner for his obedience and refuse to reward the sinner at all, in which case their status would not be similar.
            But perhaps there is a way of salvaging Anselm's argument, replacing the claim that an unpunished sin would make a sinner similar to a non-sinner before God with the claim that God's refusing to punish the sinner would (a) put the sinner in a position of greater freedom than a non-sinner and (b) makes sinfulness "resemble God" inasmuch as the sinner would be subject to no law. But "subject to no law" in (b) is ambiguous. It could mean simply "subject to no punishment" or it could also mean "subject to no code of conduct for one's behavior." Taken in the second sense, it seems obviously false, because the sinner is still subject to a code of conduct for behavior (i.e., God's) in the sense that it is still what the sinner ought to follow in his behavior, even if he is not punished for not following it. Taken in the first sense, moreover, it is hard to see what precisely is wrong with a sinners' resembling God in this sense such that it deserves punishment. And even if one concedes for the sake of argument that God should not allow sinners' behavior to go unregulated because it makes them similar to God, it is not clear why God could not rectify the situation by some other means, e.g., simply not rewarding them, as he rewards those who remain steadfast in their obedience, rather than actually punishing the sinners.
            But even if Anselm's arguments fail to establish the propriety of God's punishing sinners, it also seems that Anselm may be overstating his case. For all he needs to show is that God cannot offer sinners salvation in some way other than becoming incarnate, as LC tries, on the contrary, to establish. The conclusion that God could not, without treating them similarly, reward both sinners and non-sinners is sufficient for establishing this claim. For, on their own, sinners cannot make recompense for their sins, and thus, since God cannot reward them, he can either (a) leave them as they are or (b) enact some plan to effect their rescue. But, if one claims that God's infinite wisdom does not permit him to leave unfinished something that he has begun -- in this case his creating the human race with the purpose of offering them the opportunity for sharing in God's own life -- God will necessarily choose (b). Thus, having taken stock of some possible replies Anselm could make from things he actually says, it seems he can plausibly argue that both LC and NC are necessarily false. Against NC, Anselm can contend that this implies treating a sinner and a non-sinner in a similar manner, and this does not befit God. Against LC, he can argue that there is no intermediary form of compensation that humans can give to God, because humans do not have anything that they do not already owe to God. And because God cannot simply pardon them without some compensation, there is no intermediary means by which humans could satisfy their debt to God.[15]
Possibilities for Anselm's Strategy
            There are thus more options available to Anselm than Leftow's interpretation seems to suggest. For, if the reasoning I have provided on Anselm's behalf is sound, and my reading of him as endorsing these arguments from other parts of CDH is correct, Anselm will have a solid case against premise (7). But this is not all. For, in addition to attacking (7), Anselm can also turn on (9), as Leftow recommends, and argue that while the costs involved in God's becoming incarnate are real, they are not unjustified. Helpfully, Visser and Williams represent Anselm's argument against (9) as follows:
(p1) Necessarily, if human beings fall into sin, God offers them reconciliation.
(p2) Necessarily, if God does not become incarnate and die, God does not offer reconciliation to human beings. 
(p3) Necessarily, if human beings sin, God becomes incarnate.[16]
In this connection, one can note that the reasoning that Anselm can give against both LC and NC he can also give in favor of (p1), so for the rest of this paper, I will take the case for (p1) as having been established. In the remainder of this paper, I will trace out the case that Anselm makes for (p2).

Anselm's Support for Premise (p2):
            Having offered justification for (p1), an important element of (p2) naturally follows. The element in question is that Anselm needs to rule out the possibility that humans can, by their own aid, make restitution to God for their sins. The simple reason for this, as we have seen, is because their offense is against God, to whom human beings already owe everything they have. In consequence, human beings have nothing with which to pay God that is not already his. But, Anselm argues, with respect to the debt, it is human beings alone who owe this debt. So humanity has brought upon itself a debt that it cannot pay.[18]
            The next step in Anselm's case for (p2) is to argue that it is God alone who can pay this debt. In this connection, Anselm seems to begin to make progress with his argument for (p2) with respect to some arguments he gives for the conclusion that the debt which Adam's race has incurred against God is such that no creature can possibly make recompense for it. In discussion with Boso, Anselm asks Boso to consider
If you were to see yourself in the sight of God, and someone were to say to you, "look over there," and God were to interject, "it is totally against my will that you should look," consider for yourself in your own heart what contingency there is, in the totality of things which exist, on account of which you are obliged to take that look contrary to the will of God.[19]
Boso's response is to concede the plain point that Anselm wants to make: no contingency would justify anyone in taking the look, contrary to the will of God. Nor would it change the outcome, Anselm argues, if the entire universe were laid before one, with the ultimatum being that the universe be extirpated if one failed to look. The seemingly clear point behind Anselm's illustration is that an insult against God, i.e., a sin, constitutes, in turn, an infinite offense.
            As for the corresponding debt such an offense generates, Anselm seems to offer the following principle.
A. It is obvious that God demands recompense in proportion to the magnitude of the sin.
B. Undeniably.
A. You do not therefore give recompense if you do not give something greater than the entity on account of which you ought not to have committed the sin.[20]
In the form he offers it, however, Anselm's principle seems implausibly strong. For one thing, it would imply that no one, not even God, could possibly fulfill it, since this would require God to be greater than himself. Weakening the principle, one might suggest that one only needs to give something equal to the entity on account of which one has committed the sin. But even this seems doubtful. What does it even mean to suggest that someone gives something to another equal to that person? For example, it does not seem that I need to give a king the gift of another king in order to make recompense to him. Here, I suggest, one should charitably read Anselm as arguing the much more modest claim that to make recompense to someone, one must give something equal to that person's dignity and not something equal to that person.[21] Taken in this sense, one can contend that if God's dignity is such that it is infinite, any offense against God will also count as an infinite offense.
            The sense in which Anselm intends one to understand God's dignity seems to be one in which honor plays an important role, and honor, it seems, is a socially dependent concept. However, the concept of dignity, for one, is not necessarily tied to any particular system of social relations. (For example, many ethical systems accept as axiomatic something like inherent human dignity, or the kind of moral value or worth someone has in virtue of their status as a human being.) Anselm's concept of honor, moreover, does not seem quite like a socially bound one when one regards it as interchangeable with the concept of sin, viz, an offense against God. In this sense, one can also understand honor or dignity as God's authority, i.e., as the moral authority God commands in virtue of who he is. A king might (ultimately) derive his authority to rule -- i.e., his corresponding authority to be obeyed -- from a set of social rules or conventions that themselves presuppose a network of interpersonal social ties, but God's authority exists just in virtue of his moral status, as Creator and sustainer of the cosmos.[22]
            Understanding God's dignity in this sense, one might interpret Anselm as arguing that God deserves recompense in proportion to his dignity or honor. Here, one might object that one does not judge the required recompense of an offense just by the dignity of the being who is offended. One also judges it in accordance to the proportion of the offense. Here, it seems, Anselm would reply that because the offense is against God, and God is a being of infinite dignity, any offense against God is an offense that is infinite in value. But this seems implausibly strong in such a way that it would quickly lead to absurd results. On this analysis, taking a nickel from the church offering plate is equally an offense against God as Hitler's overseeing the Holocaust. And this will not do. But, if this last point is correct, it would seem the very concept of an infinite offense, in the sense at least that Anselm wants to use it, will be unserviceable.
            But it seems Anselm has another and, in my mind, much more persuasive argument he can give, based on a plausible idea he has already argued. For, given the fact that a creatures does not sin if and only if it honors God, it seems true on Anselm's account that only an individual creature can fulfill that creature's duty in honoring God. For, considering that every creature in Anselm's cosmos already gives to God everything it owes to God if and only if it gives everything it can give, it follows that no creature can give on behalf of another creature because no creature has any "surplus" duty or honor that it can give to God on behalf of another creature. And this last point is all Anselm needs to make his case that only God can give payment for man's offense.
            The next point Anselm tries to establish is that the only one who can make reconciliation for human sins is one who is both man and God. His reasoning for this move is quite straightforward: only man owes God a debt that he cannot pay on his own; no one but God can pay this debt; so, it is necessary that a God-man pay it. 
If, therefore, as is agreed, it is necessary that the heavenly city should have its full complement made up by members of the human race, and this cannot be the case if the recompense of which we have spoken is not paid, which no one can pay except God and no one ought to pay except man: it is necessary that a God-man should pay it.[23]
As Visser and Williams note, Anselm's speculations concerning God's intention to fill the vacancy left by the fallen angels with members from Adam's race it not entirely clear, since, from the point of view of Anselm's argument, it is logically dispensable.[24] But his main point, on the other hand, is clear: only God can pay the debt that man owes to God, and therefore it is necessary that God becomes man. Setting aside the details for whether a God-man is metaphysically possible, there is still one obstacle that Anselm's argument needs to overcome. And that is: why it is necessary that the God-man must die in order to atone for human sins?
            There are two conditions Anselm must meet to respond to this question in a satisfactory manner. First, the merit that the God-man attains through giving his life must be sufficient for satisfying the debt incurred by all human sin. Second, that which the God-man offers to God must be something that the God-man does not owe to God in virtue of his human nature. Anselm's approach for tackling the second desideratum is to  argue that human beings die only in consequence of Adam's sin.
A. You do not deny that rational creation was created righteous, and was so created for the purpose of being happy in the fact of God's delighted approval?
B. I do not deny this.
A. You will, moreover, not reckon it to be at all appropriate for God to force a creature -- whom he has created righteous for the purpose of happiness -- to be pitiably afflicted, in spite of an absence of guilt?
B. It is evident that, if the man had not sinned, God ought not to demand death from him.
A. God, therefore, did not force Christ to die, there being no sin in him. Rather he underwent death of his own accord, not out of an obedience consisting in the abandonment of his life, but out of an obedience consisting in his upholding of righteousness so bravely and pertinaciously that as a result he incurred death.[25]
The point behind Anselm's claim is that Christ, having no sin in him, was under no obligation to die, and thus was in the original state of righteousness that Adam and Eve enjoyed prior to their decision to sin.
            As for the first desideratum, Anselm seems to argue that just as an offense against God causes one to incur an infinite debt, so an act that goes above and beyond the call of duty from God also provides an infinite surplus of merit. I have already argued that the idea that a sin against God produces infinite debt is problematic. Does the same apply for the corresponding idea of infinite merit on God's part? I do not believe it does. For one, Anselm is not saying that every act on God's part is such that it produces infinite merit; in this case, it is only acts that are supererogatory.[26] In contrast, the correlative concept of sin, as a deficiency in what one owes, seems incompatible with its existing in an infinite quantity, because it simply collapses the distinction between various sins for which there seems an obvious difference. However, given the constraints that Anselm has placed on the concept of honoring God, there seems only one act that satisfies the definition for a supererogatory act on God's part. And that is God, as God-man, laying down his life when he does not owe this to God, since, for any other conceivable act, it will be such that even Christ owes it to God, in virtue of his being a man. 

Conclusion
            Thus, one is on good grounds, I conclude, for regarding (p2) as true. From this, of course, it follows that (p3) is true, assuming, as I have and have given some reason to show, that there are no difficulties with (p1). So, barring no further objections, one might provisionally conclude that Anselm's task of showing the Incarnation as a necessary means of atoning for the sins of mankind as a success (or, more modestly, at least not an obvious failure). Moreover, one interesting feature of Anselm's CDH that I hope to have illustrated in this essay is that just because Anselm gives one reason or explanation for a certain point he wants to make, it might not necessarily be the best thing he has to say on that point. Part of this dynamic has to do, perhaps, with the sort of dialogue format in which CDH in written. But whatever the explanation, I want to make clear that Anselm has much stronger philosophical resources at his disposal for tackling specific questions than many commentators have seemed to believe.

            Moreover, contrary (perhaps) to even Anselm's own intentions, the concept of punishment and the seemingly odd ruminations on God's plan to replace the fallen angels with humanity that have attracted much attention to CDH are shown to be absolutely inessential to Anselm's main argument. This carries some advantages. First, it shows that Anselm's response has no necessary connection at all with later atonement theories based on penal substitution. Second, it removes the air of cold calculation from the persona of God as Anselm discusses him in CDC, with respect to Anselm's speculations on God's original plan for the human race. Thirdly, it allows into focus (though it does not make necessary) alternative reasons for God's decision to offer atonement to Adam's race that might have seemed incompatible with the other two explanations Anselm gives for it. 


[1] Brian Leftow, "Anselm on the Cost of Salvation," in Medieval Philosophy and Theology 6 (1997), pg. 75.
[2] Leftow, 79.
[3] Leftow, 91.
[4] St. Anselm, 2.11.
[5] Visser and Williams, 219.
[6] Ibid.
[7] St. Anselm, 1.4.
[8] Sandra Visser and Thomas Williams, Anselm. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), 215-216.
[9] St. Anselm, 1.20.
[10] St. Anselm, 286.
[11] Ibid.
[12] Ibid.
[13] St. Anselm, 1.12.
[14] Ibid.
[15] Another point that Anselm might offer in support of his attack against LC and NC is that God cannot offer redemption and/or salvation to sinners because this would imply he permits them to enjoy blessedness without their deserving this, a point which he actually argues at one point (Anselm, 2.12). While I do not consider this a bad approach, it would require Anselm to defend a number of points that not everyone would likely find persuasive. One such claim is that God cannot simply make human beings righteous despite their choices to the contrary because this would violate their free will or autonomy. While this is not (I think) an implausible line of response, it would not be persuasive to someone who thought that free will was not an unconditional good or a sine qua non good for God's creating being good, and would therefore likely end in a deadlock.
[16] Visser and Williams, 223.
[17] St. Anselm, "Why God Became Man," translated by Janet Fairweather, in Anselm of Canterbury: The Complete Works. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998), 1.11.
[18] With respect to the whole of humanity being implicated in Adam's sin, one interesting lacuna in Anselm's argument is that he does not offer strong support for the claim. He does address the topic in other works he wrote, so perhaps he thought this sufficient, considering his present focus on the atonement. Nonetheless, the complete absence of its mention reveals much, perhaps, in the gulf between contemporary readers and those in Anselm's presumed audience.
[19] St. Anselm, 1.21.
[20] Ibid.
[21] It does not seem implausible, moreover, to think that this is the point Anselm was trying to make. Perhaps it was lost in the effort at translating it into English, or, alternatively, it did not come out on paper as he intended.
[22] In this sense, God's honor or authority would seem to fit much more closely the corresponding concept of a right than an honor in the conventional sense in which it is understood. Just as one has a right to be treated a certain way, e.g., not abused or mistreated, simply in virtue of one's dignity as a person, so, too, does God have the right too obeyed simply in virtue of being God.   
[23] St. Anselm, 2.6.
[24] Visser and Williams, 222.
[25] St. Anselm, 1.9.
[26] Anselm does not address the question whether God's becoming incarnate is a sine qua non condition of God's performing supererogatory acts, but perhaps there is good reason for thinking this is the case. For, as he is using the concept of something being supererogatory, Anselm seems to have in mind something that goes beyond duties. Anselm seems to affirm that God does not have duties, moreover, when he objects to God's forgiving sins without satisfaction or punishment, on the grounds that it would make sinners like God. Presumably, they would be like God in not having duties, among other things. And if this line of reasoning is correct, it would imply that God cannot perform supererogatory acts in the sense Anselm has in mind, unless God is incarnate.

No comments:

Post a Comment