(The following is taken from some remarks I recently made on a Facebook friend's wall. For the sake of anonymity, I will refuse to mention that friend's name, unless I am told otherwise.)
Imagine the following cases:
(1) A carpenter builds a shelf.
(2) A novelist writes a novel.
(3) A doctor devises a new pharmaceutical.
and, of course,
(4) A professor writes a paper on some
esoteric topic.
Surely, it's at least plausible to think that the carpenter
in (1) deserves both the recognition and the profits that he receives from
building the shelf. If someone were to take the shelf from him and sell it, it
seems the person who did this would be abusing the carpenter's right to the
recognition and the profit from building the shelf. One might also say the same
about the novelist and a novel. Surely, the novelist deserves both recognition
and credit for his writing a certain novel that he writes. And anyone who
prints copies of this novel and sells it without acknowledging the writer's
first having written it and giving the writer some share of this profit it
seems to commit an injustice against the writer. Or similarly, anyone who just
makes minor changes to the text of the novel, prints it, and then sells it
without acknowledging the author's first having written it and giving the
author due credit for it seems to commit an injustice against the author.
But
what, then, makes this case any different from the case in which the carpenter
builds a shelf? For it is the very *same* novel that is being sold in each and
every case in which one prints one. It might be a different copy in each case,
but why should that be relevant? And if the changes from the copy one illicitly
makes and sells are minor or not significant, how does this make the case
different from one in which someone just copies the novel word for word and
then sells it without acknowledgment?
And if
what I've just said is right, it will be hard I think to distinguish the case
of the novelist from that of the doctor. The product that the doctor devises is
the very same or nearly the very same in every copy that is made and
distributed. Perhaps one difference between the two is that the copies of the
medicine the doctor makes are used up after every instance in which one uses
them. But why should this be relevant for determining whether someone who makes
copies of this medicine without acknowledging the doctor does or does not
commit an injustice to the doctor in so making copies of it?
And, of
course, if these last two cases are good examples of cases in which someone has
intellectual property rights, why would this be any different in the last case,
in (4)? Perhaps one will say that no one has a copyright on the truth. And
maybe this is true (no pun intended). But it is decidedly unclear what this
means. Surely, no one has a copyright that they can claim over something just
in virtue of its being true. But this doesn't mean that someone can't claim a
copyright on a product that just *happens* to be true, and over which they
assert a right in virtue of their having devised or written that product. I
can, for example, claim ownership over a medicine that doesn't (very likely not
to my knowledge) work or for a paper containing a theorem that is (again not to
my knowledge) not right. And in this case, the medicine's not working and the
theorem's not being right doesn't affect my ownership rights over either. But then
why should the medicine's working and the theorem's being right remove my right
from the product?
But
surely, one might protest, I don't have a right to the theorem itself, for surely neither I nor anyone has a right to ownership
over anything of that sort, whatever it turns out that a theorem is. This I concede. But I never claimed that
I or anyone should have such a right, nor do I think I've claimed anything that
implies that I or anyone have such a right. What I have claimed is that, in the
case of the theorem, I or anyone else who writes it have a claim of ownership
over the paper itself.
For assume that one has ownership over a certain piece of
intellectual property, i.e., a novel, a certain drug, or an academic paper.
Now, the objection is that from:
(1) I have ownership over X,
it follows that:
(2) I have ownership over everything in X.
But from (2), we obtain an absurd result in certain
situations, namely, that
(3) I have ownership over a mathematical
theorem.
As I mentioned earlier, I readily concede that (3) is
absurd, and if my view really implies (3), I should readily abandon it. But in
response, I would point out that (2) does not follow from (1). For (2) implies
that
(4) I have ownership over the word
"London,"
because the word "London" appears in my novel or
academic paper. Nor is there any reason that is given as to why someone who
affirms (1) is actually committed to (2), i.e., no reason is given as to why
someone who affirmed (1) would, in affirming (1), have to affirm (2). Here,
perhaps the objector will try to reformulate the objection so to avoid this
difficulty. Maybe one should reformulate (2) as
(2*) I have ownership over all the things
in X that are represented by words in X.
But (2*) seems actually worse than (2). For (2*) implies
that, rather than having ownership over just the word "London," I
instead have ownership over London itself; for, clearly, the word
"London" represents the entity or thing London, the city.
Here,
perhaps the objector will try to insist that if one does not affirm that (2)
follows from (1), one will not be entitled to the claim that one deserves
recognition for having first discovered the theorem that appears in one's
academic paper. But I don't see why this is the case. If I have the right to
the recognition of having written a certain paper, I a fortiori have the right to the recognition of anything new that I
discovered and published in that paper. It is just not clear to me why someone
would have to claim ownership over, say, a certain theorem in order to be
recognized as having first discovered that theorem. And though I have property
rights over the paper containing the theorem, it does not follow that I have
rights over the theorem itself.
No comments:
Post a Comment