One would arguably be hard pressed to find a recent
philosophical theologian who has argued more powerfully and imaginatively for
Christian Universalism -- or the view that Christ, like the shepherd in the
parable of the lost sheep (Luke 15:1-7), will strive tirelessly until all human
beings come to know him and are saved by him -- than Marilyn McCord Adams. In
her article "Hell and the God of Justice," offers an interesting and,
I think, partly convincing series of arguments against what she identifies as the
"traditional doctrine of hell." That doctrine is one she understands
as an articulation of the claim that there are
... certain principles of justice [that] entail that men who
are sufficiently sinful ought to be made to suffer everlasting torment incompatible
with any happiness.[1]
Advocates of this traditional doctrine, Adams continues,
have typically defended this claim by arguing for the further assumption that
God would not measure up
to these standards of justice if he failed to condemn such men to hell.
Consequently, since God is perfectly just, and some men are sufficiently
sinful, God will condemn such men to hell on the day of judgment.[2]
Following this, Adams first offers a brief articulation of
the concept of justice that defenders of the traditional doctrine of hell (or
TDH) have implicitly assumed. The rest of her essay is devoted to offering
arguments against specific principles of justice that defenders of TDH have
used to try to bolster the doctrine or make it convincing.
First a
comment or two on the concept of justice presupposed by defenders of TDH.
According to Adams, some have conceived of justice in such a way that a person
is just if and only if (i) he is fair (i.e., treats all cases alike) and (ii)
treats no one worse than he deserves to be treated.[3]
And as Adams rightly notes, no one who conceived of justice in these terms
could rightly argue that God's perfect justice required of him that he condemn
certain sufficiently evil men to hell.
On this conception, God will be unjust only if he treats
equally sinful men differently or treats some persons worse than they deserve.
But God could avoid both of these actions if he awarded eternal salvation to
everyone without exception. The fact that he gave eternal salvation to Judas as
well as to Peter and John would no more make him unjust on this conception,
than it would show that vineyard owner in Jesus' parable (Matthew 20: 1-16) was
unjust because he gave a penny both to the men who worked all day and to the
men who worked for one hour.[4]
What the defender of TDH actually needs, according to Adams,
is that (iii) a just person treats no one better than he deserves to be
treated. For, otherwise, God could always treat such sufficiently evil men
better than they deserve and decide to rescue them from eternal torment.
Next, the
first two conceptions of justice she articulates, and then criticizes are,
first, the familiar principle of 'an eye for an eye, and a tooth for a tooth,'
or what one might call the retributive theory of justice (RTJ). The basic and
familiar idea behind RTJ is that punishment is just if and only if it is in direct
proportion to the offense that occasions the punishment. The second principle
is from Anselm's Cur Deus Homo, and is what one might call the "worthiness
of honor" theory of justice (WHTJ). This less familiar principle calls for
proportional retribution against any agent who offends the honor of anyone
whose moral status is superior to that of the one who offends. The third and
final is, borrowing from St. Thomas Aquinas, based on the idea that someone
who, in selecting a temporal good to the exclusion of his ultimate end,
actually chooses such that he prefers to eternally enjoy this temporal good
over his ultimate end. Thus, Aquinas argues, such a man is thereby justly
condemned for eternity in consequence of his choice.
Adams'
arguments against the first two principles, RTJ and WHTJ, strike me as pretty
powerful and as prima facie pretty convincing -- especially her criticisms of
RTJ. So, therefore, I'll reserve my comments for what she has to say regarding
the third principle. And as it currently stands, Aquinas's principle seems open
to objection. For as Adams observes, it simply does not follow from the fact
that someone wills to do something that in fact results in his eternal
condemnation that the person wills to
be deprived of happiness forever.[5]
(For example, perhaps the person does not know or believe that the action in
question has this direful consequence.) Nor does it follow from the fact that
someone wills to do something that, as a matter of fact, results in his being
forever deprived of happiness that the person a fortiori wills to have forever
the good obtained from it.
But as
Adams herself admits, one can, without difficulty, reformulate the principle in
such a way as to avoid these objections. At the core of Aquinas' argument is
the principle that 'to will a certain evil is just as bad as to do it.' And
taking this key insight into account, Adams suggests that
Even if it is true that human beings have only limited power
to harm others in this world, they could will to cause unlimited and
everlasting harm -- e.g., by willing to make someone totally unhappy forever.
And if to will it is as bad as to do it, they could thereby merit an unlimited
and everlasting punishment.[6]
Taking this suggestion to heart, moreover, the question,
now, is whether there's good reason for thinking that 'to will it is as bad as
to do it' is, in fact, true.
Ignoring
the largely irrelevant social context in which the primary incentive for
punishment is simply to prevent some men from harming others, Adams focuses on
the point at which 'to will it is as bad as to do it' would be actually
relevant for the purposes of settling the present doctrinal query. For, as
Christians believe, it is on judgment day that God will mete out reward and
punishment to various men on the basis of how well they lived their lives in
accordance with his will. And here,
Volitions as well as deeds determine a man's character; and
evil volitions as well as evil deeds are contrary to God's will.[7]
But, conceding that what one wills may sometimes be as bad a
reflection on one's character as the actual doing, does it follow that this is
generally true?
Not so,
Adams argues. And her argument here is based on the plausible assumption that
persisting in an evil desire forever is a worse reflection of one's moral
character than persisting in it for only a limited time. Using this principle
as the hinge of her argument, Adams introduces the fictional case of Brown, who
desires to torture another man, Black, for all eternity.
Suppose that Brown wants personally to torture Black
forever. Suppose further that Brown does torture Black for 30 years after which
Black dies of his injuries. When Black dies, Brown expresses great
disappointment that his opportunity to torture Black has come to an end.
Brown's deeds and desires show him to be very wicked. But do they reflect as
badly as would the actual everlasting torture? I do not think so. Persisting in
an evil desire forever is a sign of greater moral defect that persisting in it
for a limited time. Even though Brown strongly desires to torture Black forever
and has made a beginning on the project, it remains possible that at some later
time the desire will cease. His voluntarily continuing the torture forever,
however, involves Brown's forever continuing to desire the torture. If for no
other reason than this, torturing Black forever is a worse reflection on
Brown's character than simply willing it at some particular time.[8]
In conclusion, then, it is not a general truth that willing
something is as bad a reflection on one's character as is the actual doing.
But whether Adams' argument succeeds depends on what exact sense of "wills" or "willing"
the argument requires. For there is an ambiguity in the thesis that "it is not
generally true that what one wills is as bad a reflection on one's character as
what one actually does." Relevant to the present discussion, it could,
one, possibly mean that
(a) "it is not generally true that what one wills,
irrespective of the particular occasion and irrespective of the particular
time, is as bad a reflection on one's character as what one actually does on a
given occasion and at a particular time,"
or it could mean that
(b) "it is not generally true that what one wills, on
a given occasion and at a particular time, is as bad a reflection on
one's character as what one actually does irrespective of the particular
occasion and irrespective of the particular time,"
or it could also mean that
(c) "it is not generally true that what one wills,
irrespective of the particular occasion and irrespective of the particular
time, is as bad a reflection on one's character as what one actually does
irrespective of the particular occasion and irrespective of the particular
time,"
or, finally, it could mean that
(d) "it is not generally true that what one wills, on a
given occasion and at a given time, is as bad a reflection on one's character
as what one actually does irrespective of the particular occasion and
irrespective of the particular time.
Adams argument against the thesis is effectively that
Brown's torturing Black forever
reflects worsely on his character than his willing it at a particular time. And here she takes the example of Black dying
before Brown can torture him forever as an effective counter-example to the
thesis in question. This, in turn, requires that Adam's thesis should be
interpreted in the sense of (b).
But taken
in the sense of (b), it is not obvious that the principle is true. For it is
further ambiguous as to whether "on a given occasion and at a particular
time" from (b) means "at a specific time such that this time can
include no further time," or whether it allows one to group together
several times under the heading or the category of a single time. If taken in
the sense of "at a specific time such that this time can include no
further times," Adams' principle seems either correct or at least prima
facie plausible. If taken, however, in the sense of one's grouping together
several times under the heading or category of a single time, then it's not
obvious that the principle is true.
For while
it may be considered an at least plausible principle with respect to relatively
small groupings of times, Adam's principle would require I think much further
argument to establish its conclusion for anything larger than a small grouping.
But here is a problem. When compared to an infinite period of time, taken here
as all times t - n after t, any grouping of time will be considered an equally small
grouping of time. For, when compared to any infinite sum, any finite sum x that is less than any other finite sum y, the infinite sum will have infinitely more members than either x or y. But if the infinite sum has infinitely more members than either x or y, it follows that y is not greater than x with respect to the infinite sum. For the infinite sum will exceed either finite sum by an infinite number of its members. And if this is right, one will be simply unable to make any
effective distinction between a grouping of times that is short with respect
to, say, human reckoning with a grouping of time that is not short with respect
to human reckoning when the comparison is between the finite time and the
infinite time.
And indeed
one cannot take the "particular time" that Adam uses in her example
in the sense of "a specific time such that this time can include no
further time." For, here, Adams would need to give a plausible reason why
one should include this reading while excluding the "grouping of times"
reading. And it is just not easy to see what such a plausible reason could
be. For once one grants (1) that "particular time" can include groupings of times and (2) that all groupings of time are small when compared to an infinite amount of time, it is unclear whether one can affirm that willing to cause an infinite length of suffering for or throughout a finite duration of time actually reflects worse on one's character than one's willing to cause an infinite length of suffering for or throughout an infinite duration of time. And if the main force behind Adams' counterexample was the intuition that willing something bad for a single time or an instant does not reflect as badly on one's character as one's willing it for all times after a certain time, it is unclear whether one should be able to affirm the same for 'any' amount of finite time.
For this would require that the character-deforming effects of the total consecutive times in which Brown tortures Black are straightforwardly additive, and this principle is not only one that does not seem very plausible in itself; it is also one that Adams herself has explicitly denied (i.e., she herself denies that harms or the effects of harms are straightforwardly additive in her reply against the Retributive Theory of Punishment). That is, even if one grants that it is true that Brown's actually torturing Black for all times is worse than Brown's willing, for *any* amount of finite time, to torture Black for all times, Adams cannot consistently say that it is *because* of the fact that one includes an infinite amount of time and the other does not include an infinite amount of time that makes the one worse than the other.
For this would require that the character-deforming effects of the total consecutive times in which Brown tortures Black are straightforwardly additive, and this principle is not only one that does not seem very plausible in itself; it is also one that Adams herself has explicitly denied (i.e., she herself denies that harms or the effects of harms are straightforwardly additive in her reply against the Retributive Theory of Punishment). That is, even if one grants that it is true that Brown's actually torturing Black for all times is worse than Brown's willing, for *any* amount of finite time, to torture Black for all times, Adams cannot consistently say that it is *because* of the fact that one includes an infinite amount of time and the other does not include an infinite amount of time that makes the one worse than the other.
I therefore
conclude that Adams' argument against Aquinas' reformulated principle is not
successful. In this, my final paragraph, however, I want to identify one point
where Adams might renew her attack. Here, I do not necessarily agree with Adams
that Christian Universalism is true. I do, however, share her conviction that
there are some potential objections to TDH that require one to reformulate the
doctrine somewhat if it is to survive sustained attack. Assuming that Adams is
correct that the defender of TDH needs something like (iii) a just person
treats no one better than he deserves to be treated the defender of TDH will
possibly find himself in serious trouble if he insists on defending the
doctrine of hell on the basis of doctrinal orthodoxy (which, in practice, seems
perhaps like the most likely motivation for defending it).
For,
in addition to TDH, Christians (at least those in the Latin West) have
traditionally also accepted the view that no human being is such as to have the
power for meriting grace, without which no one can attain eternal salvation.
But from the fact that no one has it in his power to merit grace, it seems to
follow that no one has it in his power to deserve grace. For, surely, no one
deserves a certain good unless he merits it. But, according to (iii), God is
unjust if God gives to human beings anything better than they deserve. So, it
follows, God is unjust for giving grace to any human beings. Here, the options
for a defender of TDH seem to be either to (a) attack one of the premises in
this last argument or to (b) find some alternative principle that is just as
plausible as (iii) with which to replace (iii). But that is a task for another
time.
Let me begin by noting St. Augustine's response to Universalism: would you extend it to cover Lucifer and his minions?
ReplyDeleteThe Good Shepherd does indeed tirelessly pursue sinners as long as they dwell on this earth, but the rules change once one enters eternity. I believe that one is choosing for eternity in this life. Grace is always available through the Gospel and sacraments. But at some point time literally runs out; there is no future date at which to change one's mind. So what is God to do with the recalcitrant? Consider what this so-called atheist had to say:
'At the end of the day, if there was indeed some body or presence standing there to judge me, I hoped I would be judged on whether I had lived a true life, not on whether I believed in a certain book, or whether I'd been baptized. If there was indeed a god at the end of my days, I hoped he didn't say, 'But you were never a Christian, so you're going the other way from heaven.' If so, I was going to reply, 'You know what? You're right. Fine.'' Lance Armstrong
There simply is no future for this arrogant man; as Dylan sang, 'It's all over now baby blue.' There is nothing God can do short of violating his free will but to give him his foolish way. The way I look at it, he consigned himself to Hell for eternity, a la Satan. A 2nd chance would require the passage of time, which, again, is non-existent once one departs this vale of tears.
You should also know that the Holy Mother Church has always condemned Universalism as a heresy and that MMA is herself a heretic.