by Marilyn McCord Adams:
Abstract -- "Against the background of current debates about whether the regularities
of the natural world are to be seen as governed by natural laws or
explained by causal powers, medieval Aristotelians strike a distinctive
pose. When it comes to physics, biology, psychology, and cosmology,
they are all Aristotelians who locate the explanation of
quasi-regularities in inward principles of motion (formal functional
principles) that are or give rise to causal powers. Laws, by contrast,
are promulgated by voluntary agents to regulate the behavior of
voluntary agents. When it comes to the order of the world, natural
agency is one contributor. But the laws and policies of an omnipotent
God -- not least as to when, where, and how much to concur with natural
agency -- make a decisive difference. In this paper, I chart how these
contrasting explanatory factors are related by Aquinas, Scotus, and
Ockham."
Powers versus Laws: God and the Order of Nature in Aquinas, Scotus, and Ockham
Thursday, 28 February 2013
Aquinas on the Self-Evidence of God's Existence: A Short Summary and A Criticism
Is
God's Existence Self-Evident?
In
partial opposition to his first objection's contention that the first
principles of a science -- in the Aristotelian sense of "science" --
must be self-evident, Aquinas opens his response in ST Part I Question 2,
Article 1 by drawing a distinction. Though the first principles are always
self-evident in themselves, he
argues, they are "sometimes self-evident to us and sometimes not."[1] The
basis for his distinction is located in the claim that a proposition is
self-evident only if the predicate term forms part of the meaning for a subject
term. The example he uses to illustrate the idea he has in mind is that
"human beings are animals," since being human entails, in the sense
of the meaning of the subject term "human being," being an animal.
However,
he also claims, some propositions are such that not everyone has knowledge, in
the sense of self-evident knowledge, of the meanings in virtue of which the
subject term contains or logically implies a specific predicate meaning. For
example, as he cites from Boethius, there are some propositions the meaning of
which are "self-evident only to the learned"; here, the example he
uses is "that what isn't a body won't occupy space," the subject of
which, presumably, is "body" in terms of its meaning. With this
distinction in mind, then, he argues that the proposition "God
exists," while self-evident in itself, is not self-evident to us.
One
point worth touching on here before proceeding to article 2 is Aquinas's reason
for rejecting the idea that one can know that God exists merely by knowing the
meaning of the subject term "God." The preliminary suggestion Aquinas
gives for rejecting the idea is that not everyone understands the word
"God" to mean "that than which nothing greater can be
conceived." But the much more serious consideration he advances, I think,
is that, even granting that "God" had this commonly accepted meaning,
it would not follow that something matching this description exists, unless someone
were forced, on the pain of contradiction, to concede it as true. But it seems
that someone can reject that "God" has such a meaning without seeming
to contradict themselves in the process. At the same time, it is arguable that Aquinas
does not have good grounds for objecting to a demonstration for God's existence in this exact way. If he has just conceded that the proposition "God exists"
is self-evident in itself, he has also just conceded that God's existence is self-evident.
So, in principle, he does not have good reasons for objecting to an argument for
God's existence on, as one might say, ontological grounds; though he may still object to such an argument on epistemic
grounds, e.g., that God's existence is not self-evident to us.
Can
One Prove that God Exists?
However,
the strictures that Aquinas sets in place concerning the knowledge of God's
existence might seem to raise the question of how one could even begin to
acquire such knowledge, since this knowledge seems to require a scientific
demonstration (in the Aristotelian sense of a science) and Aquinas holds that a
demonstration in this sense requires the definition for a subject. Aquinas
shows that he is at least somewhat aware of this in his effort to address an
opinion from John Damascene, an authority whom Aquinas respects, that we cannot
know what God is, but only what God is not. But it is worth noting that this
concern would still exist without an endorsement of Damascene's negative
theology, considering that Aquinas has already denied that one can have
knowledge concerning God's existence simply in virtue of knowing the meaning of
the subject term "God" and the predicate term "exists." And
this last denial seems to amount to an admission that we are incapable of having knowledge of God's definition.
In
response to this last difficulty, Aquinas answers that what we generally take
God's name to mean can take the place
of God's definition with respect to the middle term normally required for a formal
demonstration. The grounds he claims for this view are that for existence
claims, i.e., whether a thing exists, the central link required for a proper
demonstration is not a thing's definition but its name, which, Aquinas argues,
"derives from its effects." Appropriately, then, he claims that there
are two distinct forms of demonstration: a demonstration from the cause to the
effect and a demonstration of the effect to the cause. The first demonstrates,
he argues, "why things are as they are," and relies (presumably) on
the definitions or meanings of their subject terms. The second demonstrates
"how things are," since, from any effect, he contends, one "can
demonstrate that its cause
exists."
However,
this approach can seem rather circular, owing to the fact that one might
question whether, in this case at least, from the fact that one can demonstrate
of something "that its cause exists" one can also know "that its
cause is God." The problem is that it is not clear how one can identify
God as "the cause" without having some prior understanding or idea,
however slight, of what God is. Denying that we can have such knowledge,
Aquinas proposes to rely on God's name as the middle term of the syllogism. One
not unimportant question, however, is how the name of God, in the exact
sense Aquinas needs for an Aristotelian demonstration, is itself known, i.e., by revelation, is known by all, etc. If this is the case, and if there is no other way of
coming to know the meaning Aquinas has in mind, one cannot have knowledge of
God's existence apart from revealed knowledge. Perhaps he does not think that one
can know about God apart from revelation, but this does seem like a very likely
explanation. And nowhere else -- to my knowledge -- does Aquinas offer an explanation for how one can come to know the meaning of the name "God" in either the sense of the proper name "God" or in the sense of the "divine names," such as First Cause, Prime Mover, etc.
Te
Velde suggests that Aquinas may presume there to be a single meaning of the name
"God," which, in its essentials, is the same for all, regardless of
whether they are "Christians, Jews, Muslims, or pagans."[2]
Whatever the merits of this proposal, the difficulty with this is that Aquinas
has already rejected, in his response to the idea that one can know that God
exists from the meaning of the word "God," that "God" has
such a universally recognized meaning.
I thus conclude that even though one might possibly consider the actual arguments Aquinas offers for proving the existence of God as a notable contribution to natural theology, one does not have good grounds for regarding his underlying "program" for natural theology, i.e., that which he offers in ST q.2 articles 1 and 2, as workable without some further development.
I thus conclude that even though one might possibly consider the actual arguments Aquinas offers for proving the existence of God as a notable contribution to natural theology, one does not have good grounds for regarding his underlying "program" for natural theology, i.e., that which he offers in ST q.2 articles 1 and 2, as workable without some further development.
Wednesday, 27 February 2013
Second Post on Aquinas's First Way: the Impossibility of an Infinite Regress of Moved Movers
Having argued that if anything is moved it is moved
by something else, Aquinas now argues that it is not possible that this
continue indefinitely.
But this cannot go on to infinity, because then
there would be no first mover, and, consequently, no other mover; seeing that
subsequent movers move only inasmuch as they are put in motion by the first
mover; as the staff moves only because it is put in motion by the hand.
Therefore it is necessary to arrive at a first mover, put in motion by no
other; and this everyone understands to be God.
Read uncharitably, this part of Aquinas's argument might seem nothing more than question-begging. That there is no First Mover is precisely the thing his opponent would question. Nor has Aquinas, the objector may continue, provided a reason not to think that the series of movers could (possibly) extend to infinity. But there is, I think, a more plausible way in which one can read him. There is a distinction that Aquinas (and later Duns Scotus) draws between a series of efficient causes ordered per accidens and a like series ordered per se. I now try to describe that distinction in some detail.
Now, the main point behind the distinction, one should note is the following:
(NIR): for any series of efficient causes ordered per se, an infinite regress of causes is not possible.
Though Aquinas elaborates on the distinction the point of which is to prove NIR somewhat in his Summa Contra Gentiles, a more detailed discussion of it is found in the writings of John Duns Scotus, Aquinas's near contemporary.
In
his own attempt at a proof for the existence of God, from his De Primo Principio, Scotus provides
three criteria for distinguishing a series ordered per accidens versus a series
ordered per se. To begin with the latter, a series ordered per se is (1) such
that all the efficient causes in the series are either dependent (with respect
to their causal efficacy) on the causes that precede them in the series, being
first in the series in the sense of depending on no other causes in the series
for their act of causing, or both are depended on and depend on other causes in
the series. Second (2), in a series ordered per se, the type of causality of at
least one of the efficient causes is of a higher type and rank, "inasmuch
as the higher cause is more perfect." Scotus also argues that (2) is a
consequence of (1) because no cause, in its exercise of its causal power, is
essentially dependent on a cause of the same type as itself. The final
difference (3) is that all of the efficient causes in a series ordered per se
are simultaneously required for the series to have causal efficacy. In this
last connection, Scotus is not explicit on whether he thinks (3) also follows
in consequence of (1), but it seems he is on good grounds in claiming so. For,
if the first cause in the series fails to exercise its causal efficacy
precisely at the same time as the second cause is required to exercise its
causal efficacy, it (the second cause) will have no causal efficacy with
respect to what it requires for bringing about its effect.
The
staple medieval example of a series ordered per se is a hand's moving a staff
to move a stone. In keeping with (2), the hand is a higher type of cause from
the staff because the hand (or, more accurately, the mind controlling the hand)
can (in some sense at least) by itself initiate movement or causal activity in
the series, whereas the staff cannot. Since the staff depends on the hand
precisely in the staff's act of causing, moreover, the example also satisfies
(1). Finally, arriving at (3), the staff and the hand must exercise their
causal activity at the same time, and therefore must both be present such that
the hand can act with the staff. The relations that obtain in virtue of (1) and
(2), one might note, are asymmetrical: if a causes b to act, it does not follow
that b causes a to act. They are also transitive: because if a causes b to act
and b causes c to act, it also follows that a causes c to act. One might object
to the claim that the relations that obtain between a and b in virtue of (1)
and (2) are that of asymmetry and transivity, on the basis that a is also
dependent on b in a's act of causing. My reply is that this response succeeds
only if one equivocates between a and b in the sense of (1) and (2), on the one
hand, and, on the other hand, a and b in the distinct sense implied by the
relations that obtain between a and b in virtue of (3). For the relation
between a and b in sense (3) is indeed symmetrical, and in this third sense it
is true both that b depends on a and that a depends on b. But this sense, I
hope is clear, is perfectly distinct from that logically implied by senses (1)
and (2).
In
contrast to a series of efficient causes ordered per se, on the other hand,
there is also a series of efficient causes ordered per accidens. Having defined
a series ordered per se in terms of (1) through (3), a simple and clear way of
explaining a series ordered per accidens is as merely a series in which (1)
through (3) do not obtain. The standard example here is that of Abraham's
begetting Isaac and Isaac's begetting Jacob. As his existence is concerned, so
the example goes, Isaac depends on Abraham's having begotten him some time in
the past. As it concerns his act of begetting Jacob, however, Isaac does not,
in any active sense, depend on Abraham. He can act so to beget Jacob even if
Abraham is no longer alive.
Each
member that is part of a series of efficient causes ordered per accidens, therefore,
is independent of any prior member so far as its causal efficacy is concerned.
In consequence, the time that separates each act of causality in the series is
also irrelevant insofar as each agent's causal efficacy is concerned. That is,
the causes need not exist simultaneously for the series as a whole to have its
causal efficacy. For this reason, then, it is possible that a series of causes
ordered per accidens stretch back infinitely into the past.
The
point of my describing this distinction between a series ordered per se and a series ordered per accidens should now be fairly clear. For Aquinas to rule out the
possibility of an infinite regress with respect to motion, he needs to argue
that the relevant classification for the series of efficient causes contained
in the series in question is ordered per se and not per accidens. In this
regard, one reasonable starting place for arguing this conclusion, perhaps, is
to see whether the example of the hand, staff, and stone, in terms of their
motion, can be explained in terms of a series ordered per accidens. That this
is an appropriate starting point, moreover, seems plausible in light of the
fact that this very illustration matches up with the example Aquinas himself
uses, as the very end of the last passage I quoted from the Summa reveals. In
any case, can the example be understood in a way that permits an infinite
regress to occur? According to William Rowe, it cannot.
That
is, no it cannot, Rowe claims, if one wishes to understand why the stone-moving
activity is now going on.[1] One
does not arrive at an explanation of the stick's present movement, in other
words, if one refuses to postulate something more than intermediate causes.
For, otherwise, he continues, the series will proceed to infinity and one will
fail to arrive at any explanation for
the motion going on with respect to the stick right at this moment.
But
is it really necessary, Rowe then asks, that one has to posit that, for
anything x such that x is an effect, x is caused by something y? Rowe is
pointing out, in other words, that Aquinas's argument seems, at this point at
least, to depend on some version of the principle of sufficient reason (PSR).
Very roughly, the version of PSR that Rowe is suggesting that Aquinas needs is
something like: "for any movement or change x, there is a fact or an
explanation y such that y explains x." While Rowe is indeed correct to
point out that Aquinas's argument does require some version of PSR in order to
be successful, this may be somewhat besides the point.
For
given the concept of change as I have argued that Aquinas understands it,
change is a process or an event that simply occurs necessarily (in the sense of
natural necessity) in light of the fact that there is an agent that is actually
F and a suitably disposed patient that is potentially F such that if, in these
circumstances, the agent can bring
about F in the patient, then it will necessarily bring about F in the patient.
The only circumstances in which the agent will fail to bring about F, moreover,
is if the patient is improperly disposed to receiving F, e.g., the patient is
either too far away from the agent or the agent's natural power to produce F or
the patient's natural power to receive F is otherwise obstructed. Thus,
assuming Aquinas's account of motion is coherent, for any movement or change x,
there will be a natural explanation y
for why x takes place. Rowe might protest this move, insisting that Aquinas
needs something stronger than natural necessity, but it is not clear why this
would be the case, since all that Aquinas, by Rowe's own admission, seems to
need is an explanation for every
change or movement that takes place; there was never any specification on
Rowe's part for a full explanation or a necessary (in some stronger sense of
necessity than natural) explanation. So, in other words, the version of PSR
that Rowe seems to believe Aquinas needs comes "for free" along with
the Aristotelian metaphysics that Aquinas accepts. The only other way, so far
as I can see, for Rowe to get around this difficulty is to attack Aquinas's
premise that anything that is changing is being changed. And I have already
given some reasons for thinking that his attack fails on this front.
Are
Infinite Regresses Really Impossible?
But
assuming that Rowe's objection is not sufficient to block the First Way, and
assuming that a series ordered per se can
explain certain sorts of motion, a question remains: why exactly is a series
ordered per se necessary to prevent an infinite regress of motion? Take the
example of the hand, the staff, and the stone. Now, it cannot be the case that
the staff is a necessary condition for the stone's being moved, because, for
one, one could move the stone with something besides a staff, and, more
importantly, someone could move the stone without the staff at all. So, at
most, Aquinas can say that the hand and the staff moving the stone are
sufficient conditions for moving it and not necessary conditions. This raises
an important question: does the hand's moving the stone still count as a series
ordered per se? In terms of the conditions necessary for something's counting
as a series ordered per se, it seems true that the hand is a higher type of
cause than the stone, in the sense that the hand can initiate movement and the
stone cannot. It is also true that the hand and the stone must both be present
at the same time. What is not necessarily true is that the stone depends on the
hand precisely in its act of causing motion, because it is not necessary that
the stone produces further motion in another thing. So, apparently, the hand
alone moving the stone is not necessarily part of a series ordered per se.
Hence, it cannot be true that all
cases of motion involve such an ordered series. But this conclusion may be too
quick.
For,
here, one must recall that the illustration was merely an analogy. For, even
with respect to the hand, the hand will be moved by the mind of the person
moving the hand, and the mind of the person will be moved by the movement of
neurons in the person's brain, etc. And all of this, it seems reasonable to
think, must take place in a finite period of time, because all motion, in the
sense of something moving from on state of potency to a state of actuality and
vice versa, takes place in a finite period. Moreover, even if one were to argue
that some of the causes in the series stretch back into an infinite period of
time, it is clear that some of the causes that cause movement in someone's
brain must be simultaneous with this movement, because the brain/mind's moving
the hand must be simultaneous with the hand's moving the staff, and also
simultaneous with the staff's moving the stone.
But,
clearly, it seems, the series of movers involving the mind, hand, etc. must
come to an end, nor do any of these items seem to have the power to initiate
movement, as this would imply that they move themselves from potency to
actuality, and this is not possible. And this is all the argument needs to
generate a potential regress stretching back until one arrives at a first
mover. Moreover, even if one were to concede that some series of motion are not
ordered per se, this would still not provide a satisfactory explanation for
those series that are, in fact, ordered per se. And this is all Aquinas would
seem to need for proving that some series must have a first mover. Thus, whether
Aquinas can succeed in showing that the first mover must be God is a question I
leave for another time. But it seems clear that, in arriving at this point, he
can do a much better job than many commentators seem to think.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)