Tuesday 12 February 2013

St. Augustine's Confessions: Book 11 (Time and Creation) [Part 2]



       

            In my last post, I helped myself to the assumption that Augustine's Confessions book eleven is based on a specific and idiosyncratic view of present time, viz., that present time is nothing more than a fleeting instant. In the current post, I hope to substantiate that interpretation and offer a closer reading of the text on which these assumptions are based. Since I offered something in the way of an argument last time for justifying parts of Augustine's view on philosophical grounds, my focus this time will just be on trying to convince you that I haven't just pulled this interpretation of Augustine out of thin air. Having showed that there are (I believe) good grounds for holding this view, I will offer critical comments regarding its cogency.

            The account of time that appears in the eleventh book of Augustine's Confessions is based on the plausible assumption that time is fundamentally tensed. 

Take the two tenses, past and future. How can they 'be' when the past is not now present and the future is not yet present? Yet if the present were always present, it would not pass into the past: it would not be time but eternity. If then, in order to be time at all, the present is so made that it passes into the past, how can we say that this present also 'is'?[1]
 
Augustine's point can be made clearer by explicit use of tense: only the present, he claims, 'is' or 'exists,' since, about the past, we can only say that it 'was' or that it 'did' exist, and, about the future, that it 'will exist.' However, if this is the case, how does the present ever transition to the past (or from the future to the present), given the assumption that only the present exists? 

            A natural reply to this question is to draw a distinction between (1) 'the present' as that segment or part of time that encompasses all current time in its totality (i.e., all existing time) and (2) 'the present' as a conventional designation for some arbitrary period of time only part of which is really present. For example, we might say that a year is present even if only a month of this year is present. But, as Augustine recognizes, such a distinction will work only if we can identify a single part of time as the present in the sense of (1), and there is reason to think that there is a difficulty in trying to describe the present as a part. 

            For, although we distinguish between long and short times: 

Nevertheless we speak of 'a long time' and 'a short time,' and it is only of the past or the future that we can say this ... But how can something be long or short which does not exist? For the past now has no existence and the future is not yet.[2]
Only the present is real; of the three modes of time, it alone exists. One would also wish to acknowledge, however, that there are times truly describable by the adjectives 'short' and 'long.' But if only the present exists, does it even make sense to describe time in terms of parts? For even if one can use part of a time, say, a month, to represent part of a year, and one stipulates that only the month is truly present, the same principle of divisibility seems to apply just as easily to a month. 

Moreover, not even a month which is current is present, but one day. If the first day, the others are future; if the last day, the others are past; any intermediary day falls between past and future.[3]
Augustine extends this thought to a single day, as well, and he draws out the illustration by noting that when the first of the hours "has the others in the future, the last one has them in the past."[4]
 
            He concludes with the observation that even the moments that make up an hour seem to flow instantaneously from one to the other. There therefore seems to be no part of the present such that this part can be identified with the present in the sense of (1). At this point commentators are not very explicit on the positive view of time to which Augustine's views seem to commit him. Gerard O'Daly, for example, denies that Augustine believed time could be reduced to something like a minimal time or an indivisible unit of time. He bases his denial on the grounds that although Augustine admits that any part of time can be  successively divided, the present cannot be reduced to an instant or an indivisible minimal time, because this would entail that the present has extension.[5] This seems to make sense; if the present has extension, it can be further divided, in which case it will not, contrary to the original assumption, be a minimal time. If the present time does not have extension, however, it seems it is more of a point or an instant than a duration of time. Yet, this is still far from giving us a clear picture of time, and what sort of metaphysical commitments it carries.  



         Like O'Daly, Gareth B. Matthews also advances the view that Augustine believed the present time to be divisible to a point or an instant.[6] Moreover, Matthews's summary of Augustine's view is particularly apt, I think: 

In fact, for any period of time we call "present," no matter how short it may be, part of it will be already past and part will still be future. Only if we consider now to be a "knife-edge," an instant without any duration at all, can we find something that is truly present. But such a "knife-edge" instant cannot be long or short; it has no duration. And so, by our initial assumption about time, namely, that times are long or short, such an instant is not time. So, it seems, there is no such thing as time.[7]
 
Matthews's illustration of Augustine's fleeting present as a knife-edge instant captures what seems like a genuine problem for this way of looking at time. If the illustration is accurate in its depiction of Augustine's view, it seems the present cannot be identified with any instant. For any such instant will simply be a dividing line between the past and the future, and a line does not have any duration. But a time necessarily seems to have a duration; for one can say of any time that it lasts; it does not make sense to say that a point lasts. 

            But Augustine has already advanced the view that neither the future nor the past exists, since the only time that exists, he thinks, is the present. This raises a problem: if the present is fleeting in the sense in which he describes it, it seems he must also concede that the present does not exist. In consequence, he must, then, either deny that any time exists, i.e., deny that time itself exists, or describe some new way of how we can talk about time without falling into the previous difficulties Augustine has mentioned. In this connection, Augustine opts for the second alternative; his strategy is to argue that the human mind measures time through the faculties of memory and anticipation. 

            In particular, Augustine's answer relies on his claim that the future and the past exist insofar as they are represented in the human mind. 

When a true narrative of the past is related, the memory produces not the actual events which have passed away but words conceived from images of them, which they fixed in the mind like imprints as they passed through the senses.[8]

The power of memory is such that the images that make up an event are imprinted upon the mind at the time they are perceived by the senses. The memory has the capacity to repeat events with an accuracy proportional to the force of their original imprint; and just as the event itself is extended or spread out in time, so the event is also extended in the memory.[9] To the question of how we can measure present time when the present, as he has argued, has no extension, Augustine replies that we measure it as it passes. Time, he insists, exists, because we measure it, and we cannot measure what does not exist.[10] In this sense, then, one can say that the past exists; it does not exist in itself, one might say, but it derives its existence from the present. 

            In terms of explaining how we can conceive of the future, Augustine cautiously stipulates that the future is real only in the sense that we make predictions regarding what will happen at some later time based on things as they are in the present. 

When therefore people speak of knowing the future, what is seen is not events which do not yet exist but their causes (that is, they really are future), but perhaps their causes or signs which already exist.[11]
 
The example Augustine uses to illustrate his theory is that of the sun's rising. The prediction is made in the present at dawn; what has been forecast is future (it does not yet exist). As Augustine perhaps has implicitly in mind, this account applies to events primarily and to things or objects in only a derivative sense. The sun, he notes, already exists; what one forecasts is its rising (an event). As applied to things, Augustine might say that a thing's causal principle or source brings the thing into being through its bringing the event into being; that is, the thing in question has the potency or power to bring an event of a certain type into being, and through bringing this event into being, it also brings another thing of a certain type into being. Thus, I can observe that a carpenter has the power by which to cause or create the event in which a chair comes into existence at some time in the future. But I cannot observe which chair it is that the carpenter brings into existence, since this chair does not exist in the present. 

            A natural question that arises at this point is whether Augustine's view provides an adequate account for the explananda it is invoked to explain. His question, one might conveniently note, can be divided into two major parts: (1) how we can talk about the past and the future if the past and the future do not exist and (2) how we can give an adequate explanation for the existence of present time if present time is simply a razor's edge or a sliver that separates the future and the past. The verdict, I believe, is a negative one. Augustine's solution to (1) is ingenious, but it does not provide a satisfactory answer to (2). 

            One can see this by noting a passage in which Augustine gives an example of how the memory recalls past events. 

Thus my boyhood, which is no longer, lies in past time which is no longer. But when I am recollecting and telling my story, I am looking on its images in present time, since it is still in my memory.[12]
 
The key locution to note from this passage is "in present time." As Augustine has already stipulated, neither past nor future times exist. He has also called into question the possibility that even the present exists by noting that the present would have to be literally a durationless instant or a point. As his answer to the problem of how the future and past exist, however, Augustine has argued they exist in the present. This does not seem coherent: if the present is merely a "razor's edge" that partitions the future and the past, it is not possible to conceive of it as a time. And if it is not a time, it cannot serve as the underlying time in which anything is recalled or forecasted. What is most surprising, to me, however, is that none of the commentators on Augustine that I have referenced (and others) have commented on this. Perhaps they simply assumed that the view went wrong elsewhere, and hence did not need criticism in this specific area; or perhaps they were distracted by the otherwise dazzling transition from the ontological features of time Augustine offers in the first part of the exposition in such a way that they did not notice the difficulty that arises when the transition is made.

       However, it would be wrong, I think, to conclude that Augustine has to conceive of present time in this way, i.e., as a razor's edge or an instant. Recall, in my last post, I offered a modified defense of Augustine's premise (12) as that premise was represented by Christopher Kirwin. That premise was 

    (12) when a time is present, every part of it is present

Now, as I noted, the argument Augustine originally offers for support of (12) is such that if one

accepted it as true, one would have to regard time as such that no time has any duration. But the

new argument that I relied on for supporting (12) does not (so far as I can tell) lead to this 

conclusion. That argument, which I will repost for convenience's sake, was this: 

       (A1) Either a duration of time d is present or it is not. 
       (A2) If it is not, then d is not present.
       (A3) If it is, then d can be divided.  
       (A4) Either d can be infinitely divided or it cannot. 
       (A5) If it cannot, then one must arrive eventually at a unit of time that is indivisible. 
       (A6) If It can, then d must contain an infinite number of countable points. 
       (A7) But it is impossible that there is an infinite number of countable points in a finite duration.
       (A8) Every duration of time can be finitely divided to a single indivisible time. 

From the premises  

        (A5) If it cannot, then one must arrive eventually at a unit of time that is indivisible.

and 

        (A7) But it is impossible that there is an infinite number of countable points in a finite duration.

the conclusion that follows (A8) does not say anything about the indivisible unit of time being a 

point  or a line (in the sense of a "razor line"). All it says is that it cannot be further divided. In this 

connection, one should not that 'instant' can be taken in one of two senses. 

          In one sense, it can be the point that, in conjunction with another such point, marks off the end 

of a line or a duration. In another sense, it can be itself a segment of time, or, more properly, the basic

unit of time, such that a  duration of time is composed of many such segments; this is how instants 

were conceived of in the middle ages, and, so far as I can tell, there seems nothing incoherent in the 

idea. And perhaps the concept is even necessary for thinking about any time; for, if time consisted 

only of durations and points (in the sense of razor lines), any time is either a duration or a point. But 

a duration cannot be composed merely of points; for a duration, in the relevent sense, contains time, 

but a point does not. And if any duration were composed of nothing but smaller durations, there

would have to be a duration such that this duration could not be halved into two smaller durations or 

segments. But if anything is a duration, it can be divided, so there is no such duration that cannot be 

halved into two smaller durations or segments. So either this process must continue indefinitely, or 

one must arrive at a smallest unit of time, i.e., a segment, that is not a duration but which, with other 

such units, makes up a duration. As the assumed premise (A7) goes, an infinite division is 

impossible. So there is such a smallest unit of time, So, I think it safe to conclude, there must be a 

unit of time that is neither a point  or a duration but that itself contains time in the smallest 

conceivable degree to which any unit can have time. 

       This, I  believe, is substantial.  For it implies that Augustine's version of presentism can be 

salvaged in a  more philosophically defensible form. I emphasize 'can' in this case because, as the 

reader might  recall, I accepted  the revised argument for (10) merely on stipulation; one would still 

have to make  good on defending  one of two crucial premises, viz., (A7), of that argument. But this 

is, I think it easy to conclude, a much better position for Augustine than merely having to concede 

that his entire view on time, or so as it appears in Confessions book eleven, is incoherent. 




[1] St. Augustine, The Confessions, translated by Henry Chadwick. (New York: Oxford University Press, 2008), 11.14.17.
[2] Augustine, 11.15.18.
[3] Augustine, 11.15.19.
[4] Augustine, 11.15.20.
[5] Gerard O'Daly, Augustine's Philosophy of Mind. (London: Gerald Duckworth & Co. Ltd., 1987), 154.
[6 Gareth B. Matthews, Augustine. (New York: Wiley-Blackwell, 2005), 180.
[7] Ibid.
[8] Augustine, 11.18.23.
[9 Augustine, 11.21. 27.
[10] Ibid.
[11] Augustine, 11.18.24.
[12] Augustine, 11.18.23.

No comments:

Post a Comment